![]() |
PHILOSOPHY MUSIC |
TRANSFORMATIONS IN ART AND AESTHTICS
I. Introduction Recent decades have
witnessed a dramatic broadening in the scope of aesthetic inquiry. No longer
focused exclusively on the arts and natural beauty, the mainstream of
aesthetics has entered a delta in which its flow has spread out into many channels
before entering the oceanic expanse that is Western civilization. Several
decades ago, environmental aesthetics began to attract interest and has grown
to be an important focus of present-day inquiry in aesthetics. Along with
environmental ethics, it has become part of the broader range of environmental
studies and the environmental movement in general. This expansion has
continued, interpreting environment not only as natural but also as social. Aesthetics
has been applied to social relations and political uses, and now, most recently
to the objects and situations of everyday life. The course of the arts has
displayed a similar succession of changes over the past century and a half, increasingly
rejecting traditional paradigms of representation and incorporating into their subject-matter
and practices the everyday world, along with active participation by their audience.
It would seem that art has overstepped all boundaries, boundaries between art
and non-art, between artist and perceiver, between art and life. Some might
say that it has lost its identity entirely. Scholars committed to
the study of the fine arts and traditional forms of natural beauty may consider
this enlargement of the arts and extension of aesthetics a corruption of the traditional
standards of those endeavors. This, of course, ignores the fact that, as an
area of scholarship, aesthetics is of comparatively recent origin, only beginning
with Baumgarten’s Aesthetica in 1750. Less dogmatic scholars may take these
changes as worth inquiry in their own right, perhaps signifying a change in the
condition of aesthetics. I should like the follow the second course here, for I
think that these developments reflect not only greater inclusiveness but a
fundamental alteration in the nature of aesthetic inquiry. Put most directly
and succinctly, this expansion changes the field of aesthetics from an
aesthetics of objects to an aesthetics of experience, an aesthetics of
sensibility. This essay proposes an account of how this has come about and
what it signifies. II. The transformations of art Developments in the
visual arts since the late nineteenth century display a fascinating succession of
movements and styles. Among the most notable movements are Impressionism,
Post-impressionism, Fauvism, Expressionism, Cubism, Futurism, Surrealism, Dada,
Abstract Art, Pop Art, Op Art, and Conceptual Art. These have provided a surprising
array of treasures for the museum-goer and rich material for the art
historian. The changes seem to puzzle the mind much as they dazzle the eye,
posing seemingly bizarre innovations that present insoluble obstacles to
efforts at understanding the meaning of modern art and frustrating attempts at
determining its boundaries. This history is, however, more than a series of changes
in style, and these changes display more than degrees and variations in representation
and abstraction. Let us look more closely at this succession of movements to
see if there is some underlying logic to their sequence. Impressionism , to
begin, is usually explained as an attempt at capturing the fleeting effects of
light, especially sunlight, on objects and landscapes. Things seem to lose
their solidity and appear to vibrate with solar energy, dissolving into vaguely-defined,
multi-colored hues as the atmosphere is charged by sunlight. With Post-impressionism
, objects regained solidity and radiated a strong presence, while Fauvism flourished
with untamed brushwork and intense hues. In Expressionism objects were colored
in the rich tones of powerful emotion, but this was then replaced by the dissolution
of solidity into the geometrical structures of Cubism , sometimes broken up
into their parts, rendered multi-perspectivally, or made transparent by
displaying their inner structure. Futurism, in contrast, transmuted the
solidity of objects into the disconcerting dynamism of frenetic motion. With
the iconoclasm of Dada, ridicule was cast at the once noble objects of artistic
idealization and bourgeois contentment by introducing the prosaic and
irreverent into the sanctorum of art, while Surrealism transformed the world
of ordinary objects into the bizarre distortions and irrational juxtapositions
of dreams. As the visual arts
became emancipated from the constraints of representation, the figurative
center of art was increasingly abandoned. Its representational subject-matter
became unimportant and the purely pictorial elements of hue, texture, form, and
composition became the source of rich originality. Artists forsook any attempt
at capturing the world of objects, and used color and form for their visual effect
alone. One could consider Pop Art the antithesis of abstraction, where common
objects and commercialized forms take center stage larger than life, or it
could be the apotheosis of abstraction, presenting stylized illustrations as
pure pictorialism. Abstraction reappeared in the subtle variation of repeated
simple forms for their pulsating effect on the eye, ingeniously exploited by Op
Art , while in Conceptual Art the object disappeared from space and became
only an imaginative construction. This kaleidoscopic
survey of the modern course of the visual arts verges on caricature, but it nonetheless
reveals a fascinating process of transfiguration. In this succession of
movements one may see imaginative transmutations of the art object under the
influence of light, of the eye, of emotion, and of dreams, along with varying
degrees of manipulation of the object’s structure, its solidity, and its
variability under the influence of thought and imagination. This is often seen
as a history of the iconoclasm of the modern artist, constantly defying
conventional expectations and traditional modes. That turns it into an account
of art movements that increasingly reject traditional paradigms and incorporate
the everyday world and the participation of the viewer. This history could then
be read as an account of the vagaries of artistic imagination coupled with the
unbridled irreverence of the artist. To be sure, one can often find such
expressions in manifestations of the artistic temperament and its inclination
to notoriety. However, I should like
to suggest another, very different reading. This is to consider the course of
modern art as a narrative of transformation, not of objects, but of experiences.
Indeed, these developments signify a shift from object-based art to
experience-based art. The account displays not so much a sequence of distorted
or abandoned objects as a progressive sequence of ways of seeing. The object
becomes less important as the visual effect increases in significance until, in
abstract and conceptual art, the object disappears entirely. From its
dissolution into light and color in Impressionism, the tactile sense of its
pure physicality and weight in Post-Impressionism, its transformation into a
stimulus for evoking an emotional response in Expressionism, its structural
dissolution in Cubism, its physical dissolution into movement in Futurism, its transition
into parody in Dada, its oneiric transmutation in Surrealism and into an ocular
stimulus in Op Art, its disappearance in abstract art in favor of the
sensibility of pictorial qualities, the lampooning effect of its parody in Pop
Art – all these have made the object less important or not important at all.
In its place is art’s effect on the spectator. But to put it this way
is actually misleading because it masks a crucial difference: the audience in
art is no longer a spectator but has become rather a participant and co-creator,
absorbing the visual or textual materials, responding physically at times to
its stimulation, and intellectually as well as emotionally to its social
critique, as in Futurism’s glorification of war and Dada’s critique of
bourgeois society, and by its participation in the creative process, activating
the art object. It is essential to understand that this transformation in the
arts did not turn appreciation into pure subjectivity, into psychological
effects disconnected from the body, the art work, and the situation. Rather
these arts demanded sharpened awareness and acute perceptual attention to their
sensible qualities. They required recognizing the effects of art as conscious
body experience: physical as well as mental. Often this was required by the perceptual
demands of the art work for active participation in an appreciative process
that collaborates with the artistic one. Indeed, these traditionally separate
functions were fused in experiencing art. We have, in short, the
transformation of an art of objects into an art of experiences. What does all
this signify? To respond to this question, let me turn to the scholarly
analogue of the artistic process. III. The transformations of
aesthetic inquiry While art has undergone
a series of transformative changes, aesthetic theory has largely remained mired
in the framework and concepts of the eighteenth century, grounded mainly in
Kant’s aesthetics. I have written at length elsewhere about the persistence of
obsolescent concepts such as aesthetic disinterestedness, contemplation, purposiveness
without purpose, the quest for universality, and the subjectivity of aesthetic
judgments, as well as questioning distinctions such as pure and adherent beauty,
the sensible and the supersensible, and aesthetics and morality.[1] Important as
these ideas may have been two centuries ago in establishing aesthetics within
the framework of a systematic philosophy and giving legitimacy and independence
to the arts, these concepts have become increasingly irrelevant to the actual
practices of artists and the appreciative experiences of the art public. Despite
being constrained by outmoded and irrelevant aesthetic concepts, aesthetic
inquiry has, in recent decades, pursued a number of directions that reflect the
expanded scope of the arts and aesthetic appreciation. And the art public has
been increasingly willing to accept the use of innovative art materials and the
widening range of art experiences that extend beyond the museum or concert hall
and into the home, the workplace, the street, and the field. More significant
still is the complete alteration of aesthetic appreciation from the receptive
contemplation of objects to an active aesthetic engagement with the materials and
conditions of art works. Nor is it any longer clear or even possible to
separate aesthetic value from moral value, as the social significance and uses
of art and the aesthetic have come into greater prominence. Further, the
increasingly political applications of the arts belies their traditional
exclusivity. Along
with the innovative approaches of the arts has come an enlargement of the scope
of aesthetic experiences, and new scholarly interests have emerged over the
last several decades. Among these are environmental aesthetics, the aesthetics
of politics, social aesthetics, including relational aesthetics, and everyday
aesthetics. The progressive broadening in the scope of aesthetic inquiry and
away from the conventional venues of art began, I think, largely by focusing
attention on the aesthetics of environment.[2]
It started with a return of attention to nature and an exploration of modes and
conditions of appreciation that differ greatly from the disinterested contemplation
of distant scenes. Walking in the woods, paddling a stream, hiking in a
wilderness, driving down a highway or along a rural road in an agricultural
landscape, and sailing a boat became recognized as occasions for aesthetic
pleasure, occasions where an intrinsic part of the enjoyment lay in entering
into some activity in the landscape. At the same time, recognition grew that
aesthetic engagement in environment embraces more than the appreciation of
nature, for a large part of environmental experience in the developed world
takes place in cities. Urban aesthetics began to enter into environmental
discourse, and including the built environment expanded the conditions and
possibilities of appreciation. Even outer space became a subject for aesthetic
awareness.[3] Recognizing
an aesthetic interest in environment has had powerful implications for
aesthetic inquiry more generally, for aesthetics has become concerned not only
with art objects but with aesthetic situations. And this shift was not only a
conceptual one but a material one: the focus of appreciation was no longer on
a discrete object but on a situation, and the traditional dualistic assumption
of Western philosophy that considered appreciation a subjective response to an
external object became increasingly inappropriate and challenged. I have
proposed replacing this model with the concept of aesthetic engagement to reflect
the embeddedness of the appreciator in every environmental context. A related
development is the formulation primarily by Chinese environmental aestheticians
of ecological aesthetics or eco-aesthetics.[4] Once
environment gained aesthetic legitimacy, it led to other enlargements of the
venues of aesthetic appreciation. One of these lies in discerning aesthetic
values in social contexts, where the aesthetic is found in situations involving
different forms of human relationships, such as friendship, family, and love. Aesthetic
values are present in other associations as well, but often in a negative
form. Indeed, negative aesthetic values are common in commercial situations,
voluntary associations and, indeed, even forms of social relations. Such
contexts have led to recognizing perceptual experiences that are common in social
situations as negative in character. Identifying such forms of aesthetic
negativity as aesthetic affront, aesthetic pain, and aesthetic depravity has
led to broadening the scope of aesthetics to include negative values. And
because these values identify harmful practices, aesthetics merges with ethics
to form a basis for social criticism.[5] A similar
development is the idea of relational aesthetics developed by the French critic
Nicolas Bourriaud.[6]
Applied to the work of a number of contemporary artists, relational aesthetics
recognizes that their art creates a social space, a context for human
relationships. The art work then becomes an occasion for human interactions
and the audience is turned into a community.[7]
This is a development in the understanding of aesthetic experience, but under
the influence of traditional aesthetics, the art world has co-opted the insight
of relational aesthetics by the practice of replacing the term ‘relational
aesthetics’ with ‘relational art,’ thus turning a situation into an
object and entirely missing the point. of relational aesthetics. The insight of
relational aesthetics remains valid, nevertheless. Political
aesthetics is yet another broadening of inquiry closely allied with social
aesthetics. Jacques Ranciére has called attention to the political
implications of sensibility: its distribution, its control, and its uses, and he
has developed this in the service of an argument for radical democracy.[8] Going about
this from another direction, Crispin Sartwell has interpreted the force of
political ideology from the fact that it is actually an aesthetic system, and
he sees politics promoting its goals by creating an aesthetic environment.[9] Employing
similar materials, Davide Panagia has related the force of an idea to the
bodily sensations that accompany it. He finds sensation at the source of political
thought and the aesthetic as the source of political action.[10] My own recent
work has joined closely both the social and the political implications of the
aesthetic. Recognizing that the heart of the aesthetic lies in sensibility, I
have claimed that developing the awareness and capacity of aesthetic
sensibility leads to immensely broader and richer social experience. At the
same time, through an awareness of negative aesthetics and the negative
sublime, aesthetic sensibility provides a powerful tool for criticism by
recognizing the human consequences of exploitative commercial and political
practices.[11] Perhaps
the most recent direction to emerge from the liberation and expansion of
aesthetic experience is what is known as the aesthetics of everyday life. Although
there is presently a flowering of work on everyday aesthetics, the possibility of
aesthetic gratification in ordinary objects and events has long been known,
even if degraded by prevalent philosophical theory. Widely valued by poets,
especially Romantic poets and those in Asian traditions, the aesthetic in
everyday situations has also been recognized by novelists, as well.[12] It may be
most convenient, though, to locate its contemporary intellectual origins in John
Dewey’s Art as Experience.[13]
In that book Dewey argued against the separation of art from life by
basing aesthetic experience on the biological and cultural conditions of human
life. He located the aesthetic, not in an internalized awareness of sensation
and feeling, but in “a complete interpenetration of self and the world of
objects and events.”[14]
Further, Dewey maintained that “the esthetic…is the clarified and intensified
development of traits that belong to every normally complete experience.”[15] I shall
not attempt a chronology of the development of the present interest in the
aesthetics of everyday life. Instead, let me mention some significant stages in
its emergence. An important source came from the innovations that were
occurring in the arts in the mid-twentieth century. A prime influence was the
work of the American composer and theorist, John Cage. Experimental and
innovative, Cage’s interest in aleatoric (chance) music became widely known through
his piano work of 1952, 4’33”, which consisted entirely in the chance occurrence
of audible sounds that occurred during that interval of time. Happenings, a
predecessor of present-day performance art that originated in the 1950s,
eliminated the separation between the art work and the viewer, who became a
participant in the work, which often comprised the unscripted, chance events of
an ordinary situation. Such
innovative developments in the arts had a profound effect on concurrent work in
aesthetics. Beginning in the 1990s, a series of steps in the expansion of
aesthetic appreciation were taken that resolutely rejected the traditional
separation of art from life activities, in the conviction that the scope of the
arts has no limits. Two books published in 1992 made an extended case for a broader
and more inclusive understanding of the aesthetic that incorporated all
activities within the purview of art. David Novitz’s The Boundaries of Art
[16]
abjured all limits to art and extended the aesthetic to personal and social
relationships, and from these to politics. My book, Art and Engagement,[17]
extended an argument I had first made in 1970 for reconstructing aesthetics
under the influence of innovative developments in the contemporary arts.[18] The argument
explored the philosophical implications of considering aesthetic appreciation in
both traditional and contemporary arts as active perceptual engagement. Two
decades later, my book elaborated a theoretical position for the enlargement of
aesthetic experience that would include the objects and events of daily life
based on the practices and experience of the arts, themselves. Since these
publications, there has been a proliferation of work developing and detailing
the unbridled extension of the aesthetic. The aesthetics of everyday life is
the most recent stage of this progressive broadening in the scope of aesthetic
inquiry that had begun with environmental aesthetics, and important work has
already appeared. The Aesthetics of Everyday Life, a collection published
in 1995, included essays on such topics as social aesthetics, the aesthetics of
place, unplanned building, landscape, sport, weather, smells and tastes, and
food.[19]
Katya Mandoki’s Everyday Aesthetics of 2007 was the first extended
treatment of the subject.[20]
An English-language version of a book that had originally been published in
Spanish in 1994, Mandoki’s Everyday Aesthetics is a far-reaching study
of aesthetic theory of unusual scope and originality centering around the
crucial role of aesthetics in the contemporary highly technological and complex
societies in which we now live. This was soon followed by another volume with
the same title and an equally distinctive and original focus, Yuriko Saito’s Everyday
Aesthetics.[21]
Richly informed by the author’s native Japanese culture and her long
experience teaching at a school of art and design, this book details the
pervasive presence and influence of the aesthetic over the many facets of
everyday life, remarkable and unremarkable alike. The most recent addition to
these extended treatments is Thomas Leddy’s The Extraordinary in the
Ordinary: The Aesthetics of Everyday Life.[22]
Leddy develops an extensive critical review of much of the literature, as well
as the current scholarly debates, leading to his own contribution in the form of
a phenomenologically-oriented approach to aesthetics. He proposes the concept
of ‘aura’ to identify the quality an object can have when experienced as
aesthetic. It is a quality that is not confined to art objects but to the
culturally-conditioned experiences of daily life. IV. Conclusion:
The transformations of aesthetic theory I have depicted
a broad landscape on these pages, rather like one of Constable’s wall-sized
canvases, and I hope it shares their realism in its theoretical and historical
perspective on developments in art and aesthetics. For besides the greater
range of interests and applications in aesthetics, these developments have
demonstrated the obsolescence of traditional concepts. Let me suggest some
implications that seem to emerge from the trends in aesthetic experience and
theory I have been detailing here. Although the authors I have mentioned may
not subscribe to all of the ideas I shall offer in my conclusion, I think that
the developments to which they have contributed support this transformation of
aesthetics. To
begin, it is clear that there is a sharp dislocation between the practices of
many contemporary artists, their art works, and the experience and behavior of
the art public, and with modern aesthetic theory, especially as it has been
formulated under the influence of Kant. That theory is grounded in a
separation between the subjectivity of aesthetic experience and the objectivity
of the art object, in a separation between beauty and utility, and in the
sequestering of the arts and natural beauty in museums and privileged views and
away from the ordinary course of human life activities. While such a theory
may be thought to honor the special aesthetic forcefulness of the noblest
artistic creations, it does so at the expense of severely constricting the
scope of aesthetic appreciation, and that belies the prevalence of aesthetic
value in human cultures. Is it possible to have a theoretical frame that
retains the validity of the sacred experience of great art and awesome natural
scenes while, at the same time, recognizing and accounting for the fact that
aesthetic interests pervade every domain of human experience? I
believe that it is possible and that we need concepts that can
accommodate both in proper proportion. These can be developed by enlarging the
scope and understanding of aesthetics. First, we need to overcome the
fragmentation that results from the many divisions drawn by traditional theory,
such as between the appreciator of art and the art object, between beauty and
utility, and between cognitive and non-cognitive experience. We need, in fact,
a unifying concept that can admit connections, mutual influences, and
reciprocity without losing the aesthetic altogether. Such a concept may be
found in the notion of an aesthetic field, an idea that embodies the
understanding that the presence and functioning of aesthetic values occur in a
context that encompasses the principal factors in the experience of aesthetic
value. The aesthetic field can accommodate artistic innovation and expanded
appreciative occasions for appreciation along with traditional arts, for it
enfolds the four functional constituents present in all: the objective, the
appreciative, the creative, and the performative, none of which can be taken
independently of the others.[23]
The
central idea in appreciation now becomes aesthetic engagement, which
recognizes the participation that active appreciation requires and that the contemporary
arts increasingly demand. We also need to recognize that the art object is no
longer the sole repository of aesthetic value and to accept that it need not
occupy an elevated status. For now the art work can be something of ordinary
use or no object at all but a perceptual experience or even only an idea. Nor
need it be complete and polished but simply a processive event, like much of
daily life. The context of appreciation has also changed along with the unity
of the art object, both of which now share the incompleteness of ordinary
experience. That is why the human environment has become the wider locus of
the aesthetic and the context in which specific questions need to be asked and
considered. We need to discern this new landscape of aesthetics. [1] Most of these ideas characteristic of traditional “modern” aesthetics find their support in Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Judgment (1790, 1793). [2] The literature here has become extensive. Some of the influential works include R. W. Hepburn, "Contemporary Aesthetics and the Neglect of Natural Beauty," in Wonder and other Essays (Edinburgh: The University Press, 1984). -----, The Reach of the Aesthetic (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2001), Arnold Berleant, The Aesthetics of Environment (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992), ------, Living in the Landscape: Toward an Aesthetics of Environment (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997), ------, Aesthetics and Environment, Theme and Variations (Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Ltd, 2005), Allen Carlson, Aesthetics and the Environment (New York: Routledge), 2000; Allen Carlson, Nature and Landscape: An Introduction to Environmental Aesthetics (New York: Columbia University Press, 2009), Yrjö Sepänmaa, The Beauty of Environment: A General Model for Environmental Aesthetics (Environmental Ethics Books, P.O. Box 310980, Denton, TX, 1993), Emily Brady, Aesthetics of the Natural Environment (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2003). [3] See “Designing Outer Space” in Arnold Berleant, The Aesthetics of Environment (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992), pp.99-113. [4] Zang Fan-ren,《生态美学导论》An Introduction to Ecological Aesthetics, A Review of the Relationship between Eco-aesthetics and Environmental Aesthetics (Beijing: The Commercial Press, 2010), in Chinese. ‘Eco-aesthetics’ is the term Zeng and his followers use as a shortened form of ‘ecological aesthetics.’ See also Cheng, Xiangzhan, “On the Four Keystones of Ecological Aesthetic Appreciation,” Tianjin Social Sciences, Vol. 5, 2012 (in Chinese), Asian Ecocriticism Reader, ed. Simon C. Estok and Won-Chung Kim (in English). [5] The literature here is small but growing. See Arnold Berleant, Sensibility and Sense: The Aesthetic Transformation of the Human World (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 2010), ----, Aesthetics beyond the Arts (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2012), Miyahara Kojiro and Fujisaka Shingo, Invitation to Social Aesthetics; Exploration of Society through Sensibility (Kyoto: Minerva Shobō, 2012) (in Japanese). An extended discussion of negative aesthetics occurs in Sensibility and Sense, pp. 155-192. [6] Originated by the art critic NIcolas Bourriaud in his 1998 book, Esthétique relationnelle (Relational Aesthetics). Bourriaud later associated this idea to the effects of the Internet on mental space. [7] See Relational Aesthetics, pp. 113, 13. [8] See Jacques Rancière, The Politics of Aesthetics: The Distribution of the Sensible , trans. Gabriel Rockhill (Continuum International, 2004). [9] Crispin Sartwell, Political Aesthetics (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2010). [10] Davide Panagia, The Political Life of Sensation (Duke University Press, 2009). [11] Arnold Berleant, Sensibility and Sense: The Aesthetic Transformation of the Human World (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 2010), ----, Aesthetics beyond the Arts (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2012). [12] Consider, for example, this passage from Daniel Deronda (1876): “[U]nder his calm and somewhat self-repressed exterior there was a fervor which made him easily find poetry and romance among the events of everyday life. And perhaps poetry and romance re as plentiful as ever in the world except for those phlegmatic natures who I suspect would in any age have regarded them as a dull form of erroneous thinking. They exist very easily in the same room with the microscope and even in railway carriages: what banishes them is the vacuum in gentlemen and lady passengers. How should all the apparatus of heaven and earth, from the farthest firmament to the tender bosom of the mother who nourished us, make poetry for a mind that has no movements of awe and tenderness, no sense of fellowship which thrills from the near to the distant, and back again from the distant to the near?” George Eliot, Daniel Deronda (1876) (New York: Knopf, 2000), p. 221. [13] John Dewey Art as Experience (1934) (New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1958). [14] John Dewey, Art as Experience, p. 19. [15] Ibid., p. 46. [16] David Novitz, The Boundaries of Art (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992). [17] Arnold Berleant, Art and Engagement (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992). [18] Arnold Berleant, "Aesthetics and the Contemporary Arts," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, XXIX, 2 (Winter l970), l55‑l68. Reprinted in The Philosophy of the Visual Arts, ed. Philip Alperson (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), and in part in Esthetics Contemporary, ed. Richard Kostelanetz, l978. [19] Aesthetics of Everyday Life, ed. Andrew Light and Jonathan M. Smith (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005. [20] Katya Mandoki, Everyday Aesthetics: Prosaics, the Play of Culture and Social Identities (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007). [21] Yuriko Saito, Everyday Aesthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). [22] Thomas Leddy, The Extraordinary in the Ordinary: The Aesthetics of Everyday Life (Peterborough, Ont: Broadview, 2012).s
[23] A further sign of the extension of the aesthetic may be seen in the annual French observance in Marseilles of a Semaine de la Pop Philosophie. See www.lesrencontresplacepublique.fr (accessed 14 August 2012). |